throbber
1
`
`3M COMPANY 2015
`Mylan Pharmaceuticals Inc. v. 3M Company
`IPR2015-02002
`
`

`
`THE NATURE AND HISTORY OF EXPERIMENTAL CONTROL
`
`By EDWIN G. BORING, Harvard University
`
`Solomon has discussed the history of the concept of control in experi-
`mental work with especial regard to the use of control groups in the design
`of experiments} finding no instance of the employment of a control group
`before the study of transfer by Thorndike and Woodworth in 19012 and
`no extensive use of control groups in experiments on transfer until Winch’s
`study in 1908.3 It is easily shown that the concept of control is basic to all
`experimental design and is,
`indeed,
`inherent in the essential relational
`nature of a fact. The purpose of this note is to analyze the concept more
`fully and to say something more about the history of both the concept and
`the word.
`
`The word control has three meanings: (1) a c/neck, in the sense of a veri-
`fication but thus also in the sense of a restraint, since verification restrains;
`
`in the sense of a checking and thus also in the sense of
`(2) a restraint,
`maintaining constancy; and (3) a guide or directing, in the sense of pro-
`ducing a precisely predetermined change, a constant and thus a restrained
`change. The word c/aecé itself has the first two meanings, though not the
`last, and the original meaning of control was c/oecté, for the word was
`counter-roll (contre-rolle), a duplicate register or account made to verify
`an official or first-made account and thus a check by a later roll upon the
`earlier. (Hence controller, which is misspelled comptroller because it has
`been thought of as meaning an accountant instead of a checker.) So the
`thought of correctness or conformity achieved by restraint runs all the way
`through the history of the word, even though what the psychologist hears
`nowadays about ‘controlling behavior’ suggests the promotion of action
`more than its restriction.4
`
`* Accepted for publication September 10, 1953.
`‘R. L. Solomon, An extension of control group design, Prycbol. Bull., 46, 1949,
`137-150.
`‘E. L. Thorndike and R. S. Woodworth, The influence of improvement in one
`mental function upon the efliciency of other functions, Ptyclaol. Rer/., 8, 1901, 247-
`261, 384-395, 553-564, esp. the eight-line paragraph on p. 558 where the use of a
`control group is described.
`’ W. H. Winch, The transfer of improvement of memory in school-children, Brit.
`I. Pry:/Jol., 2, 1908, 284-293. The article antedates the development of the statistical
`method for dealing with group differences.
`‘ Cf. B. F. Skinner, Science and Human Behavior, 1953, where the conception of
`control seems to me to be more positive than negative in the chapters entitled: The
`573
`
`This content downloaded from 216.43.235.227 on Mon, 13 Jun 2016 13: 16:32 UTC
`All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
`
`2
`
`

`
`574
`
`BORING
`
`The term control in the sense of a check or test observation or experi-
`ment came into scientific parlance in the latter half of the nineteenth
`century, as we shall see presently. By 1893 we find the New English
`Dictionary defining control as “a standard of comparison used to check
`the inferences deduced from an experiment by application of the Method
`of Difference,” which is the name of John Stuart Mill’s second method of
`experimental inquiry. The New English goes on to define control-experzl
`ment as "a test experiment with this end in view.” So control-experiment
`was definitely in the language before control group: had been thought of,
`and this concept takes us back to Mill’s four methods of experimental
`inquiry in his Logic of 1843.5
`Mill’s first method is the Method of Agreement: if A is always followed by a,
`then A is presumably the cause of 4. Mere agreement does not, however, furnish
`rigorous proof, although you may be limited to it when you lack the voluntary
`variation of events—the independent experimental variable—and are reduced to
`description only. For this reason the establishment of causal relations in biography,
`history, geology, paleontology, and even astronomy is less sure than in experimental
`science. Mill remarked that mere agreement would indicate that night is the cause of
`day, and day the cause of night, since the sequence is universal, and he noted that we
`can be more certain that agreement indicates cause when the antecedent term in the
`conjunction of events can be established at will without dependence upon other
`events. Mill was right in mistrusting the Method of Agreement, since the concurrence
`of A and 4 in sequence may mean only that both are elfects of the same sufficient
`cause, and, since if that other cause is suflicient but not necessary, it takes the Method
`of Difference to show that A and a are not necessary concomitants. It is for this
`reason that Mill suggested that the Method of Agreement is strengthened if A can
`be varied “at will,” that is to say, if A is a freely independent variable. Such a caveat,
`however, actually constitutes an extension of the Method of Agreement to include the
`Method of Difference (when variation of A includes its elimination) or the Method
`of Concomitant Variation (when A is merely changed in degree). The inference of
`causation is never safe when based upon agreement alone.
`The Method of Diflerence is Mill’s second method: if A is always followed by a,
`and not-A is always followed by fl0t‘d,
`then A is certainly the cause of a. This is
`equivalent to adding the control observation:
`if not-A,
`then not-4. Mill used the
`word control once: "It thus appears that in the study of various kinds of phenomena
`which we can, by our voluntary agency, modify or control, we can in general satisfy
`the requisitions of the Method of Difference; but that by the spontaneous operations
`of nature those requisitions are seldom fulfilled." This use of control is, however, in
`
`controlling environment; Self-control; Personal control; Group control; Economic
`control; Culture and control; and The problem of control. Certainly Solomon's
`control group has little relation to Slcinner’s group control. Even in discussion of
`experimental design the meaning of control is apt to vary. For instance, C. E. Buxton,
`in T. G. Andrews, Method: of Psychology, 1948, 73 f., in the course of two pages
`uses the word thrice as meaning maintenance of constancy of conditions and once in
`the sense of a test-observation.
`5 J. S. Mill, A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive, 1843, Bk. III, chap. 8.
`
`This content downloaded from 216.43.235.227 on Mon, 13 Jun 2016 13: 16:32 UTC
`All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
`
`3
`
`

`
`NATURE AND HISTORY or EXPERIMENTAL CONTROL
`
`575
`
`the sense of direction or guidance, whereas the Method of Difference provides control
`in the sense of a verifying check, although Mill did not make that use of the word.
`He recognized, however, the fundamental relation of his first two methods, speaking
`of the Ioint Method of Agreement and Diference, which is essentially the modern
`scientific procedure for treating contingencies when continuities are not observed.
`(The third method, the Method of Reriduer, need not concern us. If ABC is known
`to be the cause of abc, and BC the cause of bc, then A must be the cause of a, even
`though A can not be produced without BC nor thus a without 17:.)
`Mill's fourth procedure is the Method of Concomitant Variations. Nowadays we
`think of such observation as basic to all experiments and thus of Agreement and
`Diflerence as special cases of Concomitant Variation. Concomitant variation exists
`when there is a series of diflerences, and in any pair of concomitances one concomi-
`tance furnishes a comparison or control for the other. So we could get along with
`this method alone, if it were broadly enough conceived, except for the historical fact
`that the concept of control actually grew out of the consideration of the Method of
`Difference, which Mill's prestige established as independently important.
`Mill is usually taken as the authority on this matter. Thought about these prin-
`ciples is, however, historically continuous. A century earlier Hume had a similar, less
`specific discussion, which laid down rules equivalent to the Method of Difference
`and to the Joint Method of Agreement and Difference.“ Still another century earlier
`Francis Bacon discussed the collection of data by the finding of instances that agree,
`and of negative instances and cases to furnish comparison.’ In these authors the
`anticipation of Mill is quite clear if one but remembers what a century or two can
`do to both thought and its expression.
`At this point it is important to remark that every statement of fact expresses some
`kind of a difference. Even such description as is not experimental, being specific and
`thus discriminative, diflerentiates what
`is from what is not. Jevons oflered as the
`formula for a fact: “Where A is, X is; and where A is not, X is not;”‘ and that, of
`course, is also a statement of agreement and difference. Jevons remarked: "Every cor-
`rect and conclusive experiment necessarily consists in the comparison of results between
`two different combinations of circumstances.” It is plain then that i-n scientific descrip-
`tion we are not going to get away from the concept of control, although the idea
`appears with different degrees of specificity and formality in statements of experi-
`mental design. If you have an observed datum, there is always some point or frame of
`reference in respect of which the datum makes sense, and it might aid clarity of
`thought if one were -to think always of a datum set over against a relatum. (‘If A, then
`a) would be a datum, and (if not-A,
`then not-a) would be the relatum and the
`control observation, which might indeed depend upon a control-experiment to establish
`it. Again and again when agreement seems to yield certainty, it is because the control-
`observation is implied or even included in the experiment.
`Now let us examine some instances of the use of the concept of control and of the
`word control in the scientific literature of the last one hundred years.
`
`‘ David Hume, A Treatise on Human Nature, 1739, Bk. I, pt. iii, sect. 15.
`' Francis Bacon, Nor/em Organurn, 1620, Bk. II, Aph. 11-13, which deal respec-
`tively with the three principles.
`3 W. S. Jevons, Principle: of Science, '1st ed., 1874, II, 44; or 2nd ed., 1883, 433.
`’_Ievons, op. cit., 1874, II, 43; or 1883, 433.
`
`This content downloaded from 216.43.235.227 on Mon, 13 Jun 2016 13: 16:32 UTC
`All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
`
`4
`
`

`
`576
`
`BORING
`
`Control as restraint or guidance. The meaning of control as restraint or
`guidance is the common, though later, meaning of the term, and in science
`it applies to keeping experimental conditions constant and also to alter-
`ing the independent variable in accordance with precise known prede-
`termination. We do not need to hunt out instances of the scientific aspira-
`tion to keep conditions constant,
`to maintain controlled conditions or to
`vary a parameter under controlled conditions. In these contexts control,
`constancy and precision are of the essence of experimental science. Thus
`Titchener, in describing the nature of experiment, emphasized the neces-
`sity for repetition,
`isolation, and variation in the interests of good ob-
`servation, constancy of conditions and exact variation, although he did
`not use the word control.” In similar sense Murphy and Murphy have
`spoken of
`the “relatively uncontrolled observational and biographical
`studies" of children and the later "new experimental and highly controlled
`observation studies worked out" after 1915.11 We can also go back to
`Fechner who sought constancy of conditions by control of experimental
`procedures and the treatment of data: “The arrangement of experimental
`conditions,” he wrote, “the recording of observed values, the enumeration
`of errors or of right and wrong cases, as well as all the calculations based
`upon them, must be so arranged and controlled (controliren) by repetition
`and otherwise that, as far as possible, errors are avoided by the multiplica-
`tion of data, by calculation when error is otherwise unavoidable, and by
`observing an immutable integrity in the recording and conversion of
`data."12
`
`implies
`independent variable, moreover,
`Control of the experimental
`guidance as well as the maintenance of constancy, but the same admonitions
`and aspirations apply to this kind of control as to the control of conditions
`fixed throughout a particular experiment.
`Control enters into psychic research with two different meanings. Holding hands
`and touching feet with each of your neighbors in the spiritistic circle may be thought
`to promote psychic continuity, but the practice also acts as a control against fraud.
`There is also, however,
`the spirit control, who or which guides and directs the
`
`1'’ E. B. Titchener, A Text-Book of Psyclaology, 1910, 20; A Beginner's Psychology,
`1915, 22-25. The only use of the word control that I can find in these books is in
`Text-Book, 22, where Titchener remarks that “experimental control is still possible"
`even when introspection interferes with consciousness.
`“ Gardner Murphy and L. B. Murphy, Experimental Social Psychology, 1951,
`201 f., with examples of systematic arrangements for the recording of exact behavior
`and the maintenance of constancy of conditions on pp. 214-227.
`" G. T. Fechner, Elernente der Psytbop/Jysié, I, 1860, 85; and there is another
`example of the use of the word farther down on the same page: "die Wiederholung
`oder sonstige Controle an sich langweiliger Operationen."
`
`This content downloaded from 216.43.235.227 on Mon, 13 Jun 2016 13: 16:32 UTC
`All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
`
`5
`
`

`
`NATURE AND HISTORY or EXPERIMENTAL CONTROL
`
`577
`
`medium. This use of the term seems to have come in late, for Podmore makes no
`mention of it in 1902 in his excellent and thorough two-volume history of spiritual-
`ism.“ Nor did the New Englirh Dictionary give this meaning in 1893, although the
`Standard Dictionary by 1913 was saying for one meaning of control: “The intelli-
`gence (whatever its nature) which regulates the communication of messages through
`a medium or psychic."
`
`Control obrernationr, Jerier, and experiments. We come back to the
`special use of the word control in its original meaning as a check or
`standard of comparison, a relatum. If separate observations have controls
`interspersed (e.g. single points introduced among the double points which
`are used in determining the two-point limen upon the skin), then we have
`what may be called control obrerz/ationr. When the controls are or-
`ganized into series, then we have a control rerie: with which the experi-
`mental rerier is compared, as in various memory experiments. If the
`dissociation of the terms for comparison is greater and the organization of
`each more elaborate, then we begin to speak of the principal experiment
`and the control experiment. The term control experiment, as a standard
`of comparison, has now got into most of the dictionaries. Its synonym is
`text experiment. Logically there is, however, no difference between one
`kind of relatum and another except in degree of organization and formal
`independence. The basic conception, of course, appears early in experi-
`mentation, whereas the use of the word control comes later.
`
`The concept of control is pretty old and was quite obvious once the Renaissance
`had turned men's thought from theological fiat to experiment as the means for pene-
`trating into nature's secrets. Here is a story that makes the whole matter clear.
`In 1648 the Torricellian vacuum was known to physics in general and to Pascal
`in particular. This is the vacuum formed at the upper closed end of a tube which has
`first been filled with mercury and then inverted with its lower open end in a dish of
`mercury. The column of mercury falls in the tube until it is about 30 in. high and
`remains there, leaving a vacuum above it. Pascal was of the opinion that the column
`is supported by the weight of the air that presses upon the mercury in the dish (he
`was right;
`the Torricellian tube is a barometer) and that
`the column should be
`shorter at higher altitudes where the weight of the atmosphere would be less. So
`he asked his brother-in-law, Perier, who was at Clermont, to perform for him the
`obvious experiment at
`the Puy-de-Dome, a mountain in the neighborhood about
`3000 ft. (“S00 fathoms”) high as measured from the Convent at the bottom to the
`mountain's top. On Saturday, September 19th, 1648, Perier, with three friends of
`the Clermont clergy and three laymen, two Torricellian tubes, two dishes and plenty
`of mercury, set out for the Puy-de-Dome. At the foot they stopped at the Convent,
`set up both tubes, found the height of the column in each to be 26 old French
`inches Plus 31/2 Paris lines (28.04 modern inches),
`left one tube set up at the
`
`“ Frank Podmore, Modern Spiritualirm, Hirtory and Criticimz, 2 vols., 1902.
`
`This content downloaded from 2l6.43.235.227 on Mon, 13 Jun 2016 13: 16:32 UTC
`All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
`
`6
`
`

`
`578
`
`BORING
`
`Convent with Father Chastin to watch it so as to see whether it changed during the
`day, disassembled the other tube and carried it to the top of the mountain, 3000 ft.
`above the Convent and 4800 ft. above sea-level. There they set
`it up again and
`found to their excited pleasure that the height of the mercury column was only 23
`French inches and 2 Paris lines (24.71 in.), much less than it was down below just
`as Pascal had hoped it would be. To make sure they took measurements in five
`places at the top, on one side and the other of the mountain top, inside a shelter and
`outside, but the column heights were all the same. Then they came down, stopping on
`the way to take a measurement at an intermediate altitude, where the mercury column
`proved to be of intermediate height (26.65 in.). Back at the Convent, Father Chastin
`said that the other tube had not varied during the day, and then, setting up their
`second tube, the climbers found that it too again measured 26 in. 31/2 lines. These
`are reasonable determinations for these altitudes, showing about the usual one inch
`of change in the mercury column for every 1000 ft. of change in altitude.“
`In this experiment there was no elaborate design, and it took place 195 years too
`soon for the experimenters to have read John Stuart Mill's Logic, but the principle
`of control and of the Method of Difference is there. How important it was for them
`to have left a barometer at the base of the Puy-de-Dome to make sure that changes in
`the tube that they carried up the mountain were due to elevation and not to general
`atmospheric changes or to other unknown circumstances! How wise of the party at
`the top to have made the measurement under as many different conditions as they
`could think of with altitude constant! How intelligent of them to take a reading on
`the way down and thus to turn the Method of Difference into the Method of Con-
`comitant Variation!
`
`When Jevons was writing his section on “Blind or Test Experiments,” he missed
`this paradigm from Pascal (1648) but gave one from Faraday (1848) and another
`from Tyndall (1865).” Neither of these examples is in any formal sense a blind
`experiment or, as we should say today, a control experiment. They are simply ex-
`amples of the basic principle that a fact is a relationship and that you are not ready
`to make a scientific statement until you have a comparison to present. Thus Faraday,
`in the research cited by Jevons as including blind experiments, was really trying out
`what he called magnecrystallic action on a variety of difl'erent substances, finding
`that certain rules of magnetic orientation hold for crystals of bismuth and similar
`metals and that there is no magnetic action of this kind at all for the crystal-s of
`certain other metals, of which lead is one example." Faraday was engaged in what
`
`"‘ Blaise Pascal, The Phyricnl Treatirer of Parcel: the Equilibrium of Liquid: and
`the Weight of the Mars of the Air, trans. 1937, 103-108, which is mostly Perier's
`letter to Pascal about the experiment. For short accounts, see I. B. Cohen, Science,
`Servant of Man, 1948, 71 f.; J. B. Conant, Science and Common Sense, 1951, 72-74.
`Cohen says that Perier noted the continuous drop in the height of the column as he
`came down; if three points make a continuity, he did. Conant says that Pascal was at
`the foot of the mountain watching the control barometer, but that was Father Chastin.
`Pascal was waiting in Paris to hear what happened.
`“ Jevons, op. cit. (note 8), 1 ed., 1874, II, 45-45, is the section called “Blind or
`test experiments," in the chapter on “Experiment”; but the mention of Faraday’s and
`Tyndall's experiments does not appear until 2 ed., 1883, 433 f.
`“‘ Michael Faraday, Experimental Rerearche: in Electricity, 1855, III, Series xxii,
`83-136. The experiments on magnecrystallic action were performed in 1848.
`
`This content downloaded fi'0m 216.43.235.227 on Mon, 13 Jun 2016 13: 16:32 UTC
`All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
`
`7
`
`

`
`NATURE AND HISTORY OF EXPERIMENTAL CONTROL
`
`579
`
`might be called the experimental taxonomy of metallic behavior, and, now that his
`results are available to us, we can separate them into data and relata, into experi-
`ments and controls,
`though Faraday did not see his problem thus. Tyndall, in the
`place cited by Jevons, was describing an experiment in which 19 lb. of water were
`brought from room temperature to a boil in 21/; hr. by the constant rotation of a
`steel cylinder fitting tightly inside another steel cylinder and kept by a horse in rota-
`tion while immersed in the water—a demonstration that mechanical power can be
`turned into heat by friction." Presumably Jevons believed that the control here was
`the initial condition of the water at room temperature, but actually this experiment
`was an example of the Method of Concomitant Variation, for the temperature of the
`water was taken from time to time and found steadily to rise as equine energy was
`continuously converted into heat.
`
`In 1870 a new kind of control observation appeared in psychological
`experimentation,
`the Vexirverruc/9 that Vierordt—and later Riecker in
`1874——used in their determinations of the cutaneous two-point
`thresh-
`old.
`
`If you keep putting two points simultaneously down upon the skin with varying
`separations between them and keep track of the number of times each separation is
`perceived as a single impression and the number of times it is perceived double,
`then, if your chosen separations are proper, you can compute the separation at which
`a two would be felt as often as a one. That is the threshold. The observer, well trained
`to give phenomenal reports, can participate in this experiment quite successfully, but
`the naive observer is apt to make what Titchener called the stimulus-error, to report
`two often or always because he knows or guesses that the stimulator often or always
`puts two points to the skin. So Vierordt and then Riecker introduced single stimuli
`as checks upon the observer, calling them Vexirr/ermc/ae or puzzle trials-—actually
`control observations. Riecker worked with the method of constant stimuli which was
`
`still called then, after ‘Fechner’s original title, “the method of right and wrong cases.”
`It is ‘right’ to call two points two and one point one, and ‘wrong’ to call two points
`one and one point two. Actually the observers often did call one point two for there
`is a special physiological disposition for getting a two-fold impression out of a
`unitary stimulus, and these errors with the Vexiri/ermcbe were called Vexirfebler
`(paradoxial errors)?’
`that there should be as
`Later McDougall formally introduced the requirement
`many single stimuli as double and that the threshold should be 80% right for both
`
`" John Tyndall, Heat Considered a: 4 Mode of Motion, 1863, 21.
`” Karl von Vierordt, Die ‘Abhingigkeit der Ausbildung des Raumsinnes der Haut
`von Beweglichkeit der Korperteile, Zrcb. Bt'ol., 6, 1870, 53-72; Adolph Riecker,
`Versuche fiber den Raumsinn der Kopfhaut, ibid., 10, 1874, 177-201. On this experi-
`ment, the Vexin/er.mc17e and the Vexirfe/aler, see Victor Henri, Ueber die Raum-
`wa/arnelmzungen der Tartsinner, 1898, 58-89, esp. 61-66. On the nature of Vexir-
`felzler, which are no more "errors” than is any compulsive illusion, see Margaret
`Kincaid, An analysis of the psychometric function for the two-point limen with respect
`to the paradoxical error, this JOURNAL, 29, 1918, 227-232; Harry Helson and R. M.
`Burgert, Prediction and control of judgments from tactual single-point stimulation,
`ibid., 48, 1936, 609-616.
`
`This content downloaded from 216.43.235.227 on Mon, 13 Jun 2016 13: 16:32 UTC
`All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
`
`8
`
`

`
`580
`
`BORING
`
`kinds of stimuli taken together." That was good functionalism at the time and is
`nowadays good modern behaviorism: you see how adequate the subject
`is to his
`environment
`(stimulus~world) when without further knowledge he relies for in-
`formation upon the sensitivity of his receptor apparatus, but Titchener still thought
`that a trained observer should be able to judge sensory impression accurately in its
`own right, Whatever he suspected of the stimulus.” McDougall stuck by his guns
`even for educated subjects, and Henry Head and his associates used McDougall's
`method in the experiments which set up the distinction between protopathic and
`epicritic sensibility.” It
`is only recently that
`the Vexirverxuclze have come to be
`regarded as control observations, and indeed they are somewhat special for they func-
`tion as straight checks or controls for objective behavior, whereas they may also
`become directing guides in an introspective psychology where a trained observer
`needs to be checked as to whether he is reporting only on sensory impression or
`whether, committing the stimulus-error, he is trying to infer or guess the true nature
`of the stimulus-object."
`
`It was along in the 1870s that the word control began to be used in the
`sense of a check or a standard of comparison in respect of which a differ-
`ence is expected to lie.
`
`In 1874, in the first edition of his famous P/ayriologisc/ye Prycbologie, Wundt said
`that the fall-apparatus, used then to calibrate the Hipp chronoscope,
`is a control.
`Later the fall-apparatus changed its form and became and was called a control Imm-
`mer. Proper procedure is to run a series in which the times of the successive falls
`of the control hammer are measured by the Hipp chronoscope, and that series, which
`Wundt actually called a Korztrollverruc/2, gives you the variable error of the chrono-
`scope and, if you have measured the true time of fall on the chronograph, the constant
`error too.”
`Thus Wundt was ready enough to control a piece of apparatus with an objective
`check, but the only control he admitted as valid for the human observer was rigorous
`training in psychological observation. For psychological experimentation he registered
`objection to Korttrolloermcbe, Prfifungwerrucbe, Probeverwc/re and Vexirvermc/ye."
`
`“William McDougall, Cutaneous sensation, Report: of the Cambridge Anthro-
`pological Expedition to Torre: Strain, 1905, II, pt. ii, 189-195.
`“Titchener, On ethnological tests of sensation and perception, with special refer-
`ence to tests of color vision and tactile discrimination in the reports of the Cambridge
`Anthropological Expedition to Torres Straits, Proc. Amer. Pltilos. Soc., 55, 1916,
`204-236, esp. 206-215.
`2‘ Henry I-lead, Studies in Neurology, 1920, I, 26-29. The original experiment was
`Head, W. H. R. Rivers and James Sherren, The afferent nervous system from a new
`aspect, Brain, 28, 1905, 99-115 (reprinted in op. cit., 1920, 55-65); Head and Rivers,
`A human experiment in nerve division, Brain, 31, 1908, 325-450 (reprinted in op.
`L'it., 1920, 225-329).
`” Cf. E. G. Boring, The stimulus-error, this JOURNAL, 32, 1921, 449-471, which,
`paradoxically,
`interprets Titchener’s conception of the psychological point of view
`functionally.
`”Wilhelm Wundt, Grundziige der pbysiologisclyen Pryclaologie, 1st ed., 1874,
`772; 6th ed., III, 1911, 367. See also Titchener, Experimental Pryclaology, II, 1905,
`pt. ii, 340-344.
`“Wundt, op. cit., 6th ed., III, 1911, 399.
`
`This content downloaded from 216.43.235.227 on Mon, 13 Jun 2016 13: 16:32 UTC
`All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
`
`9
`
`

`
`NATURE AND HISTORY or EXPERIMENTAL CONTROL
`
`581
`
`Also in the 1870s this meaning of the word control entered biology by way of
`Darwin. In 1875 he reported on Utricularia, plants that float on foul water and that
`carry tiny bladders with valves that
`trap the insects and organic matter that get
`within the orifices of the bladders. It is a study in the taxonomy of plant behavior.
`After observing the reaction of the bladders to their normal food, “four bladders
`were tried as a control experiment," Darwin wrote. He fed them gum arabic and
`also sugar, neither of which produced the normal feeding reaction, whereas nitrate
`of ammonia did.” Later Darwin is found describing the movement of plants in
`response to irritants. He performed experiments with the radicles of peas, attaching
`to them as irritants bits of cardboard “which served as standards of comparison or
`controls."” In 1890 there was an article in Nature on the immunization of mice
`against tetanus. Immunized mice were inoculated with tetanus and failed to show its
`symptoms, but "control mice [not immunized] died within 48 hours.""’ When a
`word can be used thus casually, it may be assumed to have become established in the
`language-—-in this case in the vocabulary of biology.
`
`As experimental psychology developed, the design of its experiments be-
`came more rigorous and elaborate. Speaking approximately, we may say
`that formal design first developed in psychophysics, then in the reaction
`experiments, then in the experiments on memory.
`
`In 1900 we find Miiller and Pilzecker in their classical study of right associates
`using comparison series (Vergleirlareiben) as controls (but not so named) for the
`principal series (Hauptreilaerz). They also introduced fore-series (Vorreiberz) and
`after-series (Nacbreilaerz) and thus in a way they anticipated some of the design
`that Thorndike and Woodworth employed shortly after for their study of transfer.
`You even find in Muller and Pilzecker Hrmpzr/orreilaerz, Vergleiclworreiberz, H4145!-
`mzrbreilaerz and Vergleiclmacbrei/aerz, but the Vergleicbreilaen are control series used
`on the same observers. The control groups come later.”
`
`There can be no doubt that use of control observation, either implicit
`or explicit,
`is essential in sound experimental work. There has to be a
`relatum to give the datum significance. More definitely designed control
`series and control experiments have at the present time come into common
`use, even when control groups are not called for. Such controls go by a
`variety of names. For instance,
`in medical research one sometimes sees
`nowadays mention of the use of placebo (a dose that pleases the patient
`but has no pharmacological effect; placere,
`to please)
`introduced as a
`control in comparison observations or in control series.”
`
`" Charles Darwin, lrzrectivoraur Plarztr, 1875, chap. xvii, esp. 413.
`"" Charles Darwin and Francis Darwin, Power ofMa1/emerzt in Plants, 1881, chap.
`iii, esp. 160-163.
`2' E. H. ‘I-Iankin, A cure for tetanus and diphtheria, Nature, 45, 1890, 121-123.
`”G. E. Miiller and Alfons Pilzecker, Experimentelle Beitréige zur Lehre vom
`Gediichtniss, Zrclr. Pryrbal., Ergbd. 1, 1900.
`“Stewart Wolf, Effects of suggestion and conditioning on the action of chemical
`
`This content downloaded from 216.43.235.227 on Mon, 13 Jun 2016 13: 16:32 UTC
`All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
`
`10
`
`10
`
`

`
`5 8 2
`
`BORING
`
`When there is no acceptable hypothesis as to the independent variable
`in an experiment, it may be impossible to have a control, which may become
`available only when a good hypothesis comes along. Thus, in the experi-
`ments on extrasensory perception (ESP), control is very difficult. Control
`by restraint and guidance is common enough for every effort is made to
`keep conditions constant and to prevent fortuitous leakage of information
`to the percipient, but control as a check requires a knowledge of what is
`to be omitted if the Method of Difference is to be used. The reading of
`cards in an invisible pack is supposed to have been extrasensory when the
`reading deviates from ‘chance’ by an amount that can be accepted under
`current statistical conventions with a high level of confidence. But what is
`‘chance’? Good statisticians nowadays do not accept, as they did thirty years
`ago, the principle of insufficient reason as meaning the a priori presumption
`that wholly unconstrained coincidence will give correct guesses in only

This document is available on Docket Alarm but you must sign up to view it.


Or .

Accessing this document will incur an additional charge of $.

After purchase, you can access this document again without charge.

Accept $ Charge
throbber

Still Working On It

This document is taking longer than usual to download. This can happen if we need to contact the court directly to obtain the document and their servers are running slowly.

Give it another minute or two to complete, and then try the refresh button.

throbber

A few More Minutes ... Still Working

It can take up to 5 minutes for us to download a document if the court servers are running slowly.

Thank you for your continued patience.

This document could not be displayed.

We could not find this document within its docket. Please go back to the docket page and check the link. If that does not work, go back to the docket and refresh it to pull the newest information.

Your account does not support viewing this document.

You need a Paid Account to view this document. Click here to change your account type.

Your account does not support viewing this document.

Set your membership status to view this document.

With a Docket Alarm membership, you'll get a whole lot more, including:

  • Up-to-date information for this case.
  • Email alerts whenever there is an update.
  • Full text search for other cases.
  • Get email alerts whenever a new case matches your search.

Become a Member

One Moment Please

The filing “” is large (MB) and is being downloaded.

Please refresh this page in a few minutes to see if the filing has been downloaded. The filing will also be emailed to you when the download completes.

Your document is on its way!

If you do not receive the document in five minutes, contact support at support@docketalarm.com.

Sealed Document

We are unable to display this document, it may be under a court ordered seal.

If you have proper credentials to access the file, you may proceed directly to the court's system using your government issued username and password.


Access Government Site

We are redirecting you
to a mobile optimized page.





Document Unreadable or Corrupt

Refresh this Document
Go to the Docket

We are unable to display this document.

Refresh this Document
Go to the Docket